From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Unsolved problem in computer science:

Could an artificial general intelligence be created? If so, how?

Artificial general intelligence (AGI) is the ability of an intelligent agent to understand or learn any intellectual task that a human being can.[1][2] It is a primary goal of some artificial intelligence research and a common topic in science fiction and futures studies. AGI is also called strong AI,[3][4][5] full AI,[6] or general intelligent action,[7] although some academic sources reserve the term "strong AI" for computer programs that experience sentience or consciousness.[a]

Strong AI contrasts with weak AI (or narrow AI),[8][4] which is not intended to have general cognitive abilities; rather, weak AI is any program that is designed to solve exactly one problem. (Academic sources reserve "weak AI" for programs that do not experience consciousness or do not have a mind in the same sense people do.)[a] A 2020 survey identified 72 active AGI R&D projects spread across 37 countries.[9]

Characteristics[edit]

Various criteria for intelligence have been proposed (most famously the Turing test) but to date, there is no definition that satisfies everyone.[b]

Intelligence traits[edit]

However, there is wide agreement among artificial intelligence researchers that intelligence is required to do the following:[11]

and integrate all these skills towards common goals. Other important capabilities include:

in this world where intelligent behaviour is to be observed.[12] This would include an ability to detect and respond to hazard.[13] Many interdisciplinary approaches to intelligence (e.g. cognitive sciencecomputational intelligence and decision making) tend to emphasise the need to consider additional traits such as imagination (taken as the ability to form mental images and concepts that were not programmed in)[14] and autonomy.[15]

Computer based systems that exhibit many of these capabilities do exist (e.g. see computational creativityautomated reasoningdecision support systemrobotevolutionary computationintelligent agent), but no one has created an integrated system that excels at all these areas.

Mathematical formalisms[edit]

A mathematically precise specification of AGI was proposed by Marcus Hutter in 2000. Named AIXI, the proposed agent maximises “the ability to satisfy goals in a wide range of environments”.[16] This type of AGI, characterized by proof of the ability to maximise a mathematical definition of intelligence rather than exhibit human-like behavior,[17] is also called universal artificial intelligence.[18]

In 2015 Jan Lieke and Marcus Hutter showed that "Legg-Hutter intelligence is measured with respect to a fixed UTM. AIXI is the most intelligent policy if it uses the same UTM", a result which "undermines all existing optimality properties for AIXI".[19] This problem stems from AIXI's use of compression as a proxy for intelligence, which requires that cognition take place in isolation from the environment in which goals are pursued. This formalises a philosophical position known as Mind–body dualism[20]. There is arguably more evidence in support of enactivism -- the notion that cognition takes place within the environment in which goals are pursued.[21] Subsequently, Michael Timothy Bennett formalised enactive cognition (see enactivism) and identified an alternative proxy for intelligence called weakness [20]. The accompanying experiments (comparing weakness and compression) and mathematical proofs showed that maximising weakness results in the optimal "ability to complete a wide range of tasks" [22] or equivalently "ability to generalise" [23] (thus maximising intelligence by either definition). This also showed that if enactivism holds and Mind–body dualism does not, then compression is not necessary or sufficient for intelligence, calling into question widely held views on intelligence (see also Hutter Prize).

Regardless of the position taken with respect to cognition, whether this type of AGI exhibits human-like behavior (such as the use of natural language) would depend on many factors,[24] for example the manner in which the agent is embodied,[22] or whether it has a reward function that closely approximates human primitives of cognition like hunger, pain and so forth.[25]

Tests for confirming human-level AGI[edit]

The following tests to confirm human-level AGI have been considered:[26][27]

The Turing Test (Turing)
A machine and a human both converse unseen with a second human, who must evaluate which of the two is the machine, which passes the test if it can fool the evaluator a significant fraction of the time. Note: Turing does not prescribe what should qualify as intelligence, only that knowing that it is a machine should disqualify it.
The Coffee Test (Wozniak)
A machine is required to enter an average American home and figure out how to make coffee: find the coffee machine, find the coffee, add water, find a mug, and brew the coffee by pushing the proper buttons.
The Robot College Student Test (Goertzel)
A machine enrolls in a university, taking and passing the same classes that humans would, and obtaining a degree.
The Employment Test (Nilsson)
A machine performs an economically important job at least as well as humans in the same job.

AI-complete problems[edit]

There are many individual problems that may require general intelligence, if machines are to solve the problems as well as people do. For example, even specific straightforward tasks, like machine translation, require that a machine read and write in both languages (NLP), follow the author's argument (reason), know what is being talked about (knowledge), and faithfully reproduce the author's original intent (social intelligence). All of these problems need to be solved simultaneously in order to reach human-level machine performance.

A problem is informally known as "AI-complete" or "AI-hard", if solving it is equivalent to the general aptitude of human intelligence, or strong AI, and is beyond the capabilities of a purpose-specific algorithm.[28] AI-complete problems are hypothesised to include general computer visionnatural language understanding, and dealing with unexpected circumstances while solving any real-world problem.[29]

AI-complete problems cannot be solved with current computer technology alone, and require human computation. This property could be useful, for example, to test for the presence of humans, as CAPTCHAs aim to do; and for computer security to repel brute-force attacks.[30][31]

History[edit]

Classical AI[edit]

Modern AI research began in the mid-1950s.[32] The first generation of AI researchers were convinced that artificial general intelligence was possible and that it would exist in just a few decades.[33] AI pioneer Herbert A. Simon wrote in 1965: "machines will be capable, within twenty years, of doing any work a man can do."[34] Their predictions were the inspiration for Stanley Kubrick and Arthur C. Clarke's character HAL 9000, who embodied what AI researchers believed they could create by the year 2001. AI pioneer Marvin Minsky was a consultant[35] on the project of making HAL 9000 as realistic as possible according to the consensus predictions of the time; Crevier quotes him as having said on the subject in 1967, "Within a generation ... the problem of creating 'artificial intelligence' will substantially be solved".[36]

Several classical AI projects, such as Doug Lenat's Cyc project (that began in 1984), and Allen Newell's Soar project, were specifically directed at AGI.

However, in the early 1970s and then again in the early 90s, it became obvious that researchers had grossly underestimated the difficulty of the project. Funding agencies became skeptical of AGI and put researchers under increasing pressure to produce useful "applied AI".[c] As the 1980s began, Japan's Fifth Generation Computer Project revived interest in AGI, setting out a ten-year timeline that included AGI goals like "carry on a casual conversation".[40] In response to this and the success of expert systems, both industry and government pumped money back into the field.[38][41] However, confidence in AI spectacularly collapsed in the late 1980s, and the goals of the Fifth Generation Computer Project were never fulfilled.[42] For the second time in 20 years, AI researchers who had predicted the imminent achievement of AGI had been shown to be fundamentally mistaken. By the 1990s, AI researchers had gained a reputation for making vain promises. They became reluctant to make predictions at all[d] and to avoid any mention of "human level" artificial intelligence for fear of being labeled "wild-eyed dreamer[s]".[44]

Narrow AI research[edit]

In the 1990s and early 21st century, mainstream AI achieved far greater commercial success and academic respectability by focusing on specific sub-problems where they can produce verifiable results and commercial applications, such as artificial neural networks and statistical machine learning.[45] These "applied AI" systems are now used extensively throughout the technology industry, and research in this vein is very heavily funded in both academia and industry. Currently[when?], development on this field is considered an emerging trend, and a mature stage is expected to happen in more than 10 years.[46]

Most mainstream AI researchers hope that strong AI can be developed by combining the programs that solve various sub-problems. Hans Moravec wrote in 1988:

I am confident that this bottom-up route to artificial intelligence will one day meet the traditional top-down route more than half way, ready to provide the real world competence and the commonsense knowledge that has been so frustratingly elusive in reasoning programs. Fully intelligent machines will result when the metaphorical golden spike is driven uniting the two efforts.[47]

However, even this fundamental philosophy has been disputed; for example, Stevan Harnad of Princeton concluded his 1990 paper on the Symbol Grounding Hypothesis by stating:

The expectation has often been voiced that "top-down" (symbolic) approaches to modeling cognition will somehow meet "bottom-up" (sensory) approaches somewhere in between. If the grounding considerations in this paper are valid, then this expectation is hopelessly modular and there is really only one viable route from sense to symbols: from the ground up. A free-floating symbolic level like the software level of a computer will never be reached by this route (or vice versa) – nor is it clear why we should even try to reach such a level, since it looks as if getting there would just amount to uprooting our symbols from their intrinsic meanings (thereby merely reducing ourselves to the functional equivalent of a programmable computer).[48]

Modern artificial general intelligence research[edit]

The term "artificial general intelligence" was used as early as 1997, by Mark Gubrud[49] in a discussion of the implications of fully automated military production and operations. The term was re-introduced and popularized by Shane Legg and Ben Goertzel around 2002.[50] AGI research activity in 2006 was described by Pei Wang and Ben Goertzel[51] as "producing publications and preliminary results". The first summer school in AGI was organized in Xiamen, China in 2009[52] by the Xiamen university's Artificial Brain Laboratory and OpenCog. The first university course was given in 2010[53] and 2011[54] at Plovdiv University, Bulgaria by Todor Arnaudov. MIT presented a course in AGI in 2018, organized by Lex Fridman and featuring a number of guest lecturers.

However, as of yet, most AI researchers have devoted little attention to AGI, with some claiming that intelligence is too complex to be completely replicated in the near term. However, a small number of computer scientists are active in AGI research, and many of this group are contributing to a series of AGI conferences. The research is extremely diverse and often pioneering in nature.

Timescales: In the introduction to his 2006 book,[55] Goertzel says that estimates of the time needed before a truly flexible AGI is built vary from 10 years to over a century, but the 2007 consensus in the AGI research community seems to be that the timeline discussed by Ray Kurzweil in The Singularity is Near[56] (i.e. between 2015 and 2045) is plausible.[57] However, mainstream AI researchers have given a wide range of opinions on whether progress will be this rapid. A 2012 meta-analysis of 95 such opinions found a bias towards predicting that the onset of AGI would occur within 16–26 years for modern and historical predictions alike. It was later found that the dataset listed some experts as non-experts and vice versa.[58]

In 2017, researchers Feng Liu, Yong Shi and Ying Liu conducted intelligence tests on publicly available and freely accessible weak AI such as Google AI or Apple's Siri and others. At the maximum, these AI reached an IQ value of about 47, which corresponds approximately to a six-year-old child in first grade. An adult comes to about 100 on average. Similar tests had been carried out in 2014, with the IQ score reaching a maximum value of 27.[59][60]

In 2020, OpenAI developed GPT-3, a language model capable of performing many diverse tasks without specific training. According to Gary Grossman in a VentureBeat article, while there is consensus that GPT-3 is not an example of AGI, it is considered by some to be too advanced to classify as a narrow AI system.[61] In the same year Jason Rohrer used his GPT-3 account to develop a chatbot, and provided a chatbot-developing platform called "Project December". OpenAI asked for changes to the chatbot to comply with their safety guidelines; Rohrer disconnected Project December from the GPT-3 API.[62]

In 2022, DeepMind developed Gato, a "general-purpose" system capable of performing more than 600 different tasks.[63]

Brain simulation[edit]

Whole brain emulation[edit]

A popular discussed approach to achieving general intelligent action is whole brain emulation. A low-level brain model is built by scanning and mapping a biological brain in detail and copying its state into a computer system or another computational device. The computer runs a simulation model so faithful to the original that it will behave in essentially the same way as the original brain, or for all practical purposes, indistinguishably.[64] Whole brain emulation is discussed in computational neuroscience and neuroinformatics, in the context of brain simulation for medical research purposes. It is discussed in artificial intelligence research[57] as an approach to strong AI. Neuroimaging technologies that could deliver the necessary detailed understanding are improving rapidly, and futurist Ray Kurzweil in the book The Singularity Is Near[56] predicts that a map of sufficient quality will become available on a similar timescale to the required computing power.

Early estimates[edit]

Estimates of how much processing power is needed to emulate a human brain at various levels (from Ray Kurzweil, Anders Sandberg and Nick Bostrom), along with the fastest supercomputer from TOP500 mapped by year. Note the logarithmic scale and exponential trendline, which assumes the computational capacity doubles every 1.1 years. Kurzweil believes that mind uploading will be possible at neural simulation, while the Sandberg, Bostrom report is less certain about where consciousness arises.[65]

For low-level brain simulation, an extremely powerful computer would be required. The human brain has a huge number of synapses. Each of the 1011 (one hundred billion) neurons has on average 7,000 synaptic connections (synapses) to other neurons. It has been estimated that the brain of a three-year-old child has about 1015 synapses (1 quadrillion). This number declines with age, stabilizing by adulthood. Estimates vary for an adult, ranging from 1014 to 5×1014 synapses (100 to 500 trillion).[66] An estimate of the brain's processing power, based on a simple switch model for neuron activity, is around 1014 (100 trillion) synaptic updates per second (SUPS).[67]

In 1997, Kurzweil looked at various estimates for the hardware required to equal the human brain and adopted a figure of 1016 computations per second (cps).[e] (For comparison, if a "computation" was equivalent to one "floating-point operation" – a measure used to rate current supercomputers – then 1016 "computations" would be equivalent to 10 petaFLOPSachieved in 2011, while 1018 was achieved in 2022.) He used this figure to predict the necessary hardware would be available sometime between 2015 and 2025, if the exponential growth in computer power at the time of writing continued.

Modelling the neurons in more detail[edit]

The artificial neuron model assumed by Kurzweil and used in many current artificial neural network implementations is simple compared with biological neurons. A brain simulation would likely have to capture the detailed cellular behaviour of biological neurons, presently understood only in the broadest of outlines. The overhead introduced by full modeling of the biological, chemical, and physical details of neural behaviour (especially on a molecular scale) would require computational powers several orders of magnitude larger than Kurzweil's estimate. In addition the estimates do not account for glial cells, which are known to play a role in cognitive processes.[70]

Current research[edit]

There are some research projects that are investigating brain simulation using more sophisticated neural models, implemented on conventional computing architectures. The Artificial Intelligence System project implemented non-real time simulations of a "brain" (with 1011 neurons) in 2005. It took 50 days on a cluster of 27 processors to simulate 1 second of a model.[71] The Blue Brain project used one of the fastest supercomputer architectures in the world, IBM's Blue Gene platform, to create a real time simulation of a single rat neocortical column consisting of approximately 10,000 neurons and 108 synapses in 2006.[72] A longer-term goal is to build a detailed, functional simulation of the physiological processes in the human brain: "It is not impossible to build a human brain and we can do it in 10 years," Henry Markram, director of the Blue Brain Project said in 2009 at the TED conference in Oxford.[73] There have also been controversial claims to have simulated a cat brain.[citation needed] Neuro-silicon interfaces have been proposed as an alternative implementation strategy that may scale better.[74]

Hans Moravec addressed the above arguments ("brains are more complicated", "neurons have to be modeled in more detail") in his 1997 paper "When will computer hardware match the human brain?".[69] He measured the ability of existing software to simulate the functionality of neural tissue, specifically the retina. His results do not depend on the number of glial cells, nor on what kinds of processing neurons perform where.

The actual complexity of modeling biological neurons has been explored in OpenWorm project that was aimed on complete simulation of a worm that has only 302 neurons in its neural network (among about 1000 cells in total). The animal's neural network has been well documented before the start of the project. However, although the task seemed simple at the beginning, the models based on a generic neural network did not work. Currently, the efforts are focused on precise emulation of biological neurons (partly on the molecular level), but the result cannot be called a total success yet.

Criticisms of simulation-based approaches[edit]

A fundamental criticism of the simulated brain approach derives from embodied cognition where human embodiment is taken as an essential aspect of human intelligence. Many researchers believe that embodiment is necessary to ground meaning.[75] If this view is correct, any fully functional brain model will need to encompass more than just the neurons (i.e., a robotic body). Goertzel[57] proposes virtual embodiment (like in Second Life), but it is not yet known whether this would be sufficient.

Desktop computers using microprocessors capable of more than 109 cps (Kurzweil's non-standard unit "computations per second", see above) have been available since 2005. According to the brain power estimates used by Kurzweil (and Moravec), this computer should be capable of supporting a simulation of a bee brain, but despite some interest[76] no such simulation exists.[citation needed] There are several reasons for this:

  1. The neuron model seems to be oversimplified (see next section).
  2. There is insufficient understanding of higher cognitive processes[f] to establish accurately what the brain's neural activity (observed using techniques such as functional magnetic resonance imaging) correlates with.
  3. Even if our understanding of cognition advances sufficiently, early simulation programs are likely to be very inefficient and will, therefore, need considerably more hardware.
  4. The brain of an organism, while critical, may not be an appropriate boundary for a cognitive model. To simulate a bee brain, it may be necessary to simulate the body, and the environment. The Extended Mind thesis formalizes the philosophical concept, and research into cephalopods has demonstrated clear examples of a decentralized system.[78]

In addition, the scale of the human brain is not currently well-constrained. One estimate puts the human brain at about 100 billion neurons and 100 trillion synapses.[79][80] Another estimate is 86 billion neurons of which 16.3 billion are in the cerebral cortex and 69 billion in the cerebellum.[81] Glial cell synapses are currently unquantified but are known to be extremely numerous.

Philosophical perspective[edit]

"Strong AI" as defined in philosophy[edit]

In 1980, philosopher John Searle coined the term "strong AI" as part of his Chinese room argument.[82] He wanted to distinguish between two different hypotheses about artificial intelligence:[g]

  • Strong AI hypothesis: An artificial intelligence system can "think", have "a mind" and "consciousness".
  • Weak AI hypothesis: An artificial intelligence system can (only) act like it thinks and has a mind and consciousness.

The first one he called "strong" because it makes a stronger statement: it assumes something special has happened to the machine that goes beyond all its abilities that we can test – the behavior of a "weak AI" machine would be precisely identical to a "strong AI" machine, but the latter would also have subjective conscious experience. This usage is also common in academic AI research and textbooks.[83]

Mainstream AI is only interested in how a program behaves. According to Russell and Norvig, "as long as the program works, they don't care if you call it real or a simulation."[84] If the program can behave as if it has a mind, then there's no need to know if it actually has mind – indeed, there would be no way to tell. For AI research, Searle's "weak AI hypothesis" is equivalent to the statement "artificial general intelligence is possible". Thus, according to Russell and Norvig, "most AI researchers take the weak AI hypothesis for granted, and don't care about the strong AI hypothesis."[84] Thus, for academic AI research, "Strong AI" and "AGI" are two very different things.

In contrast to Searle and mainstream AI, some futurists such as Ray Kurzweil use the term "strong AI" to mean "human level artificial general intelligence".[56] This is not the same as Searle's strong AI, unless you assume that consciousness is necessary for human-level AGI. Academic philosophers such as Searle do not believe that is the case, and artificial intelligence researchers do not care.[84]

Consciousness[edit]

There are other aspects of the human mind besides intelligence that are relevant to the concept of strong AI which play a major role in science fiction and the ethics of artificial intelligence:

These traits have a moral dimension, because a machine with this form of strong AI may have rights, analogous to the rights of non-human animals. As such, preliminary work has been conducted on approaches to integrating full ethical agents with existing legal and social frameworks. These approaches have focused on the legal position and rights of 'strong' AI.[86] Bill Joy, among others, argues a machine with these traits may be a threat to human life or dignity.[87]

It remains to be shown whether any of these traits are necessary for strong AI. The role of consciousness is not clear, and currently there is no agreed test for its presence. If a machine is built with a device that simulates the neural correlates of consciousness, would it automatically have self-awareness? It is also possible that some of these properties, such as sentience, naturally emerge from a fully intelligent machine. It's also possible that it will become natural to ascribe these properties to machines once they begin to act in a way that is clearly intelligent.

Artificial consciousness research[edit]

Although the role of consciousness in strong AI/AGI is debatable, many AGI researchers[77] regard research that investigates possibilities for implementing consciousness as vital. In an early effort Igor Aleksander[88] argued that the principles for creating a conscious machine already existed but that it would take forty years to train such a machine to understand language[clarification needed].

Possible explanations for the slow progress of strong AI research[edit]

Since the launch of AI research in 1956, progress in this field of creating machines skilled with intelligent action at the human level has slowed.[89] One basic potential explanation for this delay is that computers lack a sufficient scope of memory, processing power, or chip flexibility to accommodate computer-science-oriented and/or neuroscience-oriented platforms.[89][90][91] In addition, the level of complexity involved in AI research likely also limits the progress of strong AI research.[89]

Conceptual limitations are another possible reason for the slowness in AI research.[89] AI researchers may need to modify the conceptual framework of their discipline in order to provide a stronger base and contribution to the quest of achieving strong AI. This means situating a strong AI in a sociocultural context where human-like AI derives from human-like experiences. As William Clocksin wrote in 2003: "the framework starts from Weizenbaum's observation that intelligence manifests itself only relative to specific social and cultural contexts".[89]

A fundamental paradox arising from this problem is that AI researchers have only been able to create computers that can perform jobs that are complicated for people to do, such as mathematics, but conversely they have struggled to develop a computer that is capable of carrying out tasks that are simple for humans to do, such as walking (Moravec's paradox).[89] The problem as described by David Gelernter is that some people assume thinking and reasoning are equivalent.[92] The idea of whether thoughts and the creator of those thoughts are isolated individually or must be socially situated has intrigued AI researchers.[92]

The problems encountered in AI research over the past decades have further impeded the progress of AGI research and development through generating a degree of distrust in the field. The failed predictions of success promised by AI researchers and the lack of a complete understanding of human behaviors have helped diminish optimism in the primary idea of creating human-level AI.[57] Although the waxing and waning progress of AI research has brought both improvement and disappointment,[93] most investigators are optimistic about achieving the goal of AGI in the 21st century.[57]

Other possible reasons have been proposed for the slow progress towards strong AI. The intricacy of scientific problems and the need to fully understand the human brain through psychology and neurophysiology have limited many researchers in the task of emulating the function of the human brain in computer hardware through initiatives like the Human Brain Project.[94][95][96] Many researchers tend to underestimate any doubt that is involved with future predictions of AI, but without taking issues like human brain modelling seriously, AGI researchers then overlook solutions to problematic questions.[57]

However, Clocksin states that a conceptual limitation that may impede the progress of AI research is that AI researchers may be using the wrong techniques for computer programs and for the implementation of equipment.[89] When AI researchers first began to aim for AGI, a main interest was to emulate and investigate human reasoning.[97] At the time, researchers hoped to establish computational models of human knowledge through reasoning and to find out how to design a computer with a specific cognitive task.[97]

In response, the practice of abstraction, which people tend to redefine when working with a particular context in research, provides AI researchers with the option to concentrate on just a few concepts.[97] The most productive use of abstraction in AI research comes from planning and problem solving.[97] Although the aim is to increase the speed of a computation, the role of abstraction operators has posed problems.[98]

Another possible reason for the slowness in strong AI progress relates to the acknowledgement by many AI researchers that human heuristics is still vastly superior to computer performance.[94] Nonetheless, the specific functions that are programmed into increasingly powerful computers may be able to account for many of the requirements in heuristics that eventually allow AI to match human intelligence. Thus, while heuristics is not necessarily a fundamental barrier to achieving strong AI, it is widely agreed to be a challenge.

Finally, many AI researchers have debated whether or not machines should be created with emotions.[99] There are no emotions in typical models of AI, and some researchers say programming emotions into machines allows them to have a mind of their own.[89] However, emotion sums up the experiences of humans because it allows them to remember those experiences.[92] David Gelernter writes, "No computer will be creative unless it can simulate all the nuances of human emotion."[92] Thus, just as this concern over emotion has posed problems for AI researchers, it is likely to continue to challenge the concept of strong AI as its research progresses.[100][101]

Controversies and dangers[edit]

Feasibility[edit]

As of 2022, AGI remains speculative[102][103] as no such system has yet been demonstrated. Opinions vary both on whether and when artificial general intelligence will arrive. At one extreme, AI pioneer Herbert A. Simon speculated in 1965 that "machines will be capable, within twenty years, of doing any work a man can do". However, this prediction failed to come true. Microsoft co-founder Paul Allen believed that such intelligence is unlikely in the 21st century because it would require "unforeseeable and fundamentally unpredictable breakthroughs" and a "scientifically deep understanding of cognition".[104] Writing in The Guardian, roboticist Alan Winfield claimed the gulf between modern computing and human-level artificial intelligence is as wide as the gulf between current space flight and practical faster-than-light spaceflight.[105]

As such, the basic concern is whether or not strong AI is fundamentally achievable, even after centuries of effort. While most AI researchers believe strong AI can be achieved in the future, some individuals, like Hubert Dreyfus and Roger Penrose, deny the possibility of achieving strong AI.[89][106] One fundamental problem is that while humans are complex, they are not general intelligences. Various computer scientists, like John McCarthy, believe human-level AI will be accomplished, but that the present level of progress is such that a date cannot accurately be predicted.[94] AI experts' views on the feasibility of AGI wax and wane, and may have seen a resurgence in the 2010s. Four polls conducted in 2012 and 2013 suggested that the median guess among experts for when they would be 50% confident AGI would arrive was 2040 to 2050, depending on the poll, with the mean being 2081. Of the experts, 16.5% answered with "never" when asked the same question but with a 90% confidence instead.[107][108] Further current AGI progress considerations can be found above Tests for confirming human-level AGI.

Yet it is worth noting that there is no scientific rigour in such predictions. Rodney Brooks notes the findings of a report by Stuart Armstrong and Kaj Sotala, of the Machine Intelligence Research Institute, that "over that 60 year time frame there is a strong bias towards predicting the arrival of human level AI as between 15 and 25 years from the time the prediction was made". They also analyzed 95 predictions made between 1950 and the present on when human level AI will come about. They show that there is no difference between predictions made by experts and non-experts.[109]

Potential threat to human existence[edit]

The thesis that AI poses an existential risk for humans, and that this risk needs much more attention than it currently gets, has been endorsed by many public figures; perhaps the most famous are Elon MuskBill Gates, and Stephen Hawking. The most notable AI researcher to endorse the thesis is Stuart J. Russell, but many others, like Roman Yampolskiy and Alexey Turchin, also support the basic thesis of a potential threat to humanity.[110][86][111] Endorsers of the thesis sometimes express bafflement at skeptics: Gates states he does not "understand why some people are not concerned",[112] and Hawking criticized widespread indifference in his 2014 editorial:

So, facing possible futures of incalculable benefits and risks, the experts are surely doing everything possible to ensure the best outcome, right? Wrong. If a superior alien civilisation sent us a message saying, 'We'll arrive in a few decades,' would we just reply, 'OK, call us when you get here–we'll leave the lights on?' Probably not–but this is more or less what is happening with AI.[113]

A 2021 systematic review of the risks associated with AGI conducted by researchers from the Centre for Human Factors and Sociotechnical Systems of the University of the Sunshine Coast in Australia, while noting the paucity of data, found the following potential threats: "AGI removing itself from the control of human owners/managers, being given or developing unsafe goals, development of unsafe AGI, AGIs with poor ethics, morals and values; inadequate management of AGI, and existential risks".[114]

Many of the scholars who are concerned about existential risk believe that the best way forward would be to conduct (possibly massive) research into solving the difficult "control problem" to answer the question: what types of safeguards, algorithms, or architectures can programmers implement to maximize the probability that their recursively-improving AI would continue to behave in a friendly, rather than destructive, manner after it reaches superintelligence?[86][115] Solving the control problem is complicated by the AI arms race,[116][117] which will almost certainly see the militarization and weaponization of AGI by more than one nation-state, i.e., resulting in AGI-enabled warfare, and in the case of AI misalignment, AGI-directed warfare, potentially against all humanity.[118][119]

The thesis that AI can pose existential risk also has many strong detractors. Skeptics sometimes charge that the thesis is crypto-religious, with an irrational belief in the possibility of superintelligence replacing an irrational belief in an omnipotent God; at an extreme, Jaron Lanier argues that the whole concept that current machines are in any way intelligent is "an illusion" and a "stupendous con" by the wealthy.[120]

Much of existing criticism argues that AGI is unlikely in the short term. Computer scientist Gordon Bell argues that the human race will destroy itself before it reaches the technological singularityGordon Moore, the original proponent of Moore's Law, declares that "I am a skeptic. I don't believe [a technological singularity] is likely to happen, at least for a long time. And I don't know why I feel that way."[121] Former Baidu Vice President and Chief Scientist Andrew Ng states AI existential risk is "like worrying about overpopulation on Mars when we have not even set foot on the planet yet."[122]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. Jump up to:a b See below for the origin of the term "strong AI", and see the academic definition of "strong AI" and weak AI in the article Chinese room.
  2. ^ AI founder John McCarthy writes: "we cannot yet characterize in general what kinds of computational procedures we want to call intelligent."[10] (For a discussion of some definitions of intelligence used by artificial intelligence researchers, see philosophy of artificial intelligence.)
  3. ^ The Lighthill report specifically criticized AI's "grandiose objectives" and led the dismantling of AI research in England.[37] In the U.S., DARPA became determined to fund only "mission-oriented direct research, rather than basic undirected research".[38][39]
  4. ^ As AI founder John McCarthy writes "it would be a great relief to the rest of the workers in AI if the inventors of new general formalisms would express their hopes in a more guarded form than has sometimes been the case."[43]
  5. ^ In "Mind Children"[68] 1015 cps is used. More recently, in 1997,[69] Moravec argued for 108 MIPS which would roughly correspond to 1014 cps. Moravec talks in terms of MIPS, not "cps", which is a non-standard term Kurzweil introduced.
  6. ^ In Goertzels' AGI book, Yudkowsky proposes 5 levels of organisation that must be understood – code/data, sensory modality, concept & category, thought, and deliberation (consciousness) – in order to use the available hardware.[77]
  7. ^ As defined in a standard AI textbook: "The assertion that machines could possibly act intelligently (or, perhaps better, act as if they were intelligent) is called the 'weak AI' hypothesis by philosophers, and the assertion that machines that do so are actually thinking (as opposed to simulating thinking) is called the 'strong AI' hypothesis."[67]
  8. ^ Note that consciousness is difficult to define. A popular definition, due to Thomas Nagel, is that it "feels like" something to be conscious. If we are not conscious, then it doesn't feel like anything. Nagel uses the example of a bat: we can sensibly ask "what does it feel like to be a bat?" However, we are unlikely to ask "what does it feel like to be a toaster?" Nagel concludes that a bat appears to be conscious (i.e. has consciousness) but a toaster does not.[85]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Hodson, Hal (1 March 2019). "DeepMind and Google: the battle to control artificial intelligence"1843Archived from the original on 7 July 2020. Retrieved 7 July 2020AGI stands for Artificial General Intelligence, a hypothetical computer program...
  2. ^ Shevlin, Henry; Vold, Karina; Crosby, Matthew; Halina, Marta (4 October 2019). "The limits of machine intelligence: Despite progress in machine intelligence, artificial general intelligence is still a major challenge"EMBO Reports20 (10): e49177. doi:10.15252/embr.201949177ISSN 1469-221XPMC 6776890PMID 31531926.
  3. ^ Kurzweil 2005, p. 260.
  4. Jump up to:a b Kurzweil, Ray (5 August 2005a), "Long Live AI"Forbes, archived from the original on 14 August 2005: Kurzweil describes strong AI as "machine intelligence with the full range of human intelligence."
  5. ^ Treder, Mike (10 August 2005), "Advanced Human Intelligence"Responsible Nanotechnologyarchived from the original on 16 October 2019
  6. ^ "The Age of Artificial Intelligence: George John at TEDxLondonBusinessSchool 2013"Archived from the original on 26 February 2014. Retrieved 22 February 2014.
  7. ^ Newell & Simon 1976, This is the term they use for "human-level" intelligence in the physical symbol system hypothesis.
  8. ^ "The Open University on Strong and Weak AI". Archived from the original on 25 September 2009. Retrieved 8 October 2007.
  9. ^ Baum, Seth, A Survey of Artificial General Intelligence Projects for Ethics, Risk, and Policy (PDF), Global Catastrophic Risk Institute Working Paper 20, archived (PDF) from the original on 14 November 2021, retrieved 13 January 2022
  10. ^ McCarthy, John (2007a). "Basic Questions"Stanford UniversityArchived from the original on 26 October 2007. Retrieved 6 December2007.
  11. ^ This list of intelligent traits is based on the topics covered by major AI textbooks, including: Russell & Norvig 2003Luger & Stubblefield 2004,Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998 and Nilsson 1998.
  12. ^ Pfeifer, R. and Bongard J. C., How the body shapes the way we think: a new view of intelligence (The MIT Press, 2007). ISBN 0-262-16239-3
  13. ^ White, R. W. (1959). "Motivation reconsidered: The concept of competence". Psychological Review66 (5): 297–333. doi:10.1037/h0040934PMID 13844397.
  14. ^ Johnson 1987
  15. ^ de Charms, R. (1968). Personal causation. New York: Academic Press.
  16. ^ Hutter, Marcus (2005). Universal Artificial Intelligence: Sequential Decisions Based on Algorithmic Probability. Texts in Theoretical Computer Science an EATCS Series. Springer. doi:10.1007/b138233ISBN 978-3-540-26877-2Archived from the original on 19 July 2022. Retrieved 19 July 2022.
  17. ^ Legg, Shane (2008). Machine Super Intelligence (PDF) (Thesis). University of Lugano. Archived (PDF) from the original on 15 June 2022. Retrieved 19 July 2022.
  18. ^ Goertzel, Ben (2014). "Artificial General Intelligence: Concept, State of the Art, and Future Prospects"Journal of Artificial General Intelligence. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. 8598doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09274-4ISBN 978-3-319-09273-7S2CID 8387410.
  19. ^ Leike, Jan; Hutter, Marcus (2015). Bad Universal Priors and Notions of Optimality. The 28th Conference on Learning Theory. arXiv:1510.04931Archived from the original on 6 December 2022. Retrieved 6 December2022.
  20. Jump up to:a b Bennett, Michael Timothy (2022). "Computable artificial general intelligence". arXiv:2205.10513 [cs.AI].
  21. ^ Ward, Dave; Silverman, David; Villalobos, Mario (2017). "Introduction: The Varieties of Enactivism"Topoi36 (1): 365–375. doi:10.1007/s11245-017-9484-6S2CID 247434831.
  22. Jump up to:a b Bennett, Michael Timothy (2021). Symbol Emergence and The Solutions to Any Task. 14th Conference on Artificial General Intelligence. arXiv:2109.01281doi:10.1007/978-3-030-93758-4_4Archived from the original on 19 July 2022. Retrieved 19 July 2022.
  23. ^ Chollet, Francois (2019). "On the Measure of Intelligence". arXiv:1911.01547 [cs.AI].
  24. ^ Bennett, Michael Timothy; Maruyama, Yoshihiro (2022). "Philosophical Specification of Empathetic Ethical Artificial Intelligence"IEEE Transactions on Cognitive and Developmental Systems14 (2): 292–300. arXiv:2107.10715doi:10.1109/TCDS.2021.3099945S2CID 236170941Archived from the original on 6 December 2022. Retrieved 6 December 2022.
  25. ^ Bennett, Michael Timothy; Maruyama, Yoshihiro (2021). The Artificial Scientist. 14th Conference on Artificial General Intelligence. arXiv:2110.01831doi:10.1007/978-3-030-93758-4_6Archived from the original on 19 July 2022. Retrieved 19 July 2022.
  26. ^ Muehlhauser, Luke (11 August 2013). "What is AGI?". Machine Intelligence Research Institute. Archived from the original on 25 April 2014. Retrieved 1 May 2014.
  27. ^ "What is Artificial General Intelligence (AGI)? | 4 Tests For Ensuring Artificial General Intelligence"Talky Blog. 13 July 2019. Archived from the original on 17 July 2019. Retrieved 17 July 2019.
  28. ^ Shapiro, Stuart C. (1992). "Artificial Intelligence" (PDF). In Stuart C. Shapiro (ed.). Encyclopedia of Artificial Intelligence (Second ed.). New York: John Wiley. pp. 54–57. Archived (PDF) from the original on 1 February 2016. (Section 4 is on "AI-Complete Tasks".)
  29. ^ Yampolskiy, Roman V. (2012). Xin-She Yang (ed.). "Turing Test as a Defining Feature of AI-Completeness" (PDF)Artificial Intelligence, Evolutionary Computation and Metaheuristics (AIECM): 3–17. Archived(PDF) from the original on 22 May 2013.
  30. ^ Luis von Ahn, Manuel Blum, Nicholas Hopper, and John Langford. CAPTCHA: Using Hard AI Problems for Security Archived 4 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine. In Proceedings of Eurocrypt, Vol. 2656 (2003), pp. 294–311.
  31. ^ Bergmair, Richard (7 January 2006). "Natural Language Steganography and an "AI-complete" Security Primitive". CiteSeerCiteSeerX 10.1.1.105.129.
  32. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 48–50
  33. ^ "Andreas Kaplan (2022) Artificial Intelligence, Business and Civilization - Our Fate Made in Machines"Archived from the original on 6 May 2022. Retrieved 12 March 2022.
  34. ^ Simon 1965, p. 96 quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 109
  35. ^ "Scientist on the Set: An Interview with Marvin Minsky"Archived from the original on 16 July 2012. Retrieved 5 April 2008.
  36. ^ Marvin Minsky to Darrach (1970), quoted in Crevier (1993, p. 109).
  37. ^ Lighthill 1973Howe 1994
  38. Jump up to:a b NRC 1999, "Shift to Applied Research Increases Investment".
  39. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 115–117; Russell & Norvig 2003, pp. 21–22.
  40. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 211, Russell & Norvig 2003, p. 24 and see also Feigenbaum & McCorduck 1983
  41. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 161–162, 197–203, 240; Russell & Norvig 2003, p. 25.
  42. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 209–212
  43. ^ McCarthy, John (2000). "Reply to Lighthill". Stanford University. Archived from the original on 30 September 2008. Retrieved 29 September2007.
  44. ^ Markoff, John (14 October 2005). "Behind Artificial Intelligence, a Squadron of Bright Real People"The New York TimesArchived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 18 February 2017At its low point, some computer scientists and software engineers avoided the term artificial intelligence for fear of being viewed as wild-eyed dreamers.
  45. ^ Russell & Norvig 2003, pp. 25–26
  46. ^ "Trends in the Emerging Tech Hype Cycle". Gartner Reports. Archivedfrom the original on 22 May 2019. Retrieved 7 May 2019.
  47. ^ Moravec 1988, p. 20
  48. ^ Harnad, S (1990). "The Symbol Grounding Problem". Physica D42 (1–3): 335–346. arXiv:cs/9906002Bibcode:1990PhyD...42..335Hdoi:10.1016/0167-2789(90)90087-6S2CID 3204300.
  49. ^ Gubrud 1997
  50. ^ "Who coined the term "AGI"? » goertzel.org"Archived from the original on 28 December 2018. Retrieved 28 December 2018., via Life 3.0: 'The term "AGI" was popularized by... Shane Legg, Mark Gubrud and Ben Goertzel'
  51. ^ Wang & Goertzel 2007
  52. ^ "First International Summer School in Artificial General Intelligence, Main summer school: June 22 – July 3, 2009, OpenCog Lab: July 6-9, 2009"Archived from the original on 28 September 2020. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  53. ^ "Избираеми дисциплини 2009/2010 - пролетен триместър" [Elective courses 2009/2010 - spring trimester]. Факултет по математика и информатика [Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics] (in Bulgarian). Archived from the original on 26 July 2020. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  54. ^ "Избираеми дисциплини 2010/2011 - зимен триместър" [Elective courses 2010/2011 - winter trimester]. Факултет по математика и информатика [Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics] (in Bulgarian). Archived from the original on 26 July 2020. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  55. ^ Goertzel & Pennachin 2006.
  56. Jump up to:a b c (Kurzweil 2005, p. 260) or see Advanced Human IntelligenceArchived 30 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine where he defines strong AI as "machine intelligence with the full range of human intelligence."
  57. Jump up to:a b c d e f Goertzel 2007.
  58. ^ Katja Grace (2016). "Error in Armstrong and Sotala 2012"AI Impacts(blog). Archived from the original on 4 December 2020. Retrieved 24 August 2020.
  59. ^ Liu, Feng; Shi, Yong; Liu, Ying (2017). "Intelligence Quotient and Intelligence Grade of Artificial Intelligence". Annals of Data Science4 (2): 179–191. arXiv:1709.10242Bibcode:2017arXiv170910242Ldoi:10.1007/s40745-017-0109-0S2CID 37900130.
  60. ^ Brien, Jörn (5 October 2017). "Google-KI doppelt so schlau wie Siri"[Google AI is twice as smart as Siri - but a six-year-old beats both] (in German). Archived from the original on 3 January 2019. Retrieved 2 January 2019.
  61. ^ Grossman, Gary (3 September 2020). "We're entering the AI twilight zone between narrow and general AI"VentureBeatArchived from the original on 4 September 2020. Retrieved 5 September 2020Certainly, too, there are those who claim we are already seeing an early example of an AGI system in the recently announced GPT-3 natural language processing (NLP) neural network. ... So is GPT-3 the first example of an AGI system? This is debatable, but the consensus is that it is not AGI. ... If nothing else, GPT-3 tells us there is a middle ground between narrow and general AI.
  62. ^ Quach, Katyanna. "A developer built an AI chatbot using GPT-3 that helped a man speak again to his late fiancée. OpenAI shut it down". The Register. Archived from the original on 16 October 2021. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
  63. ^ Wiggers, Kyle (13 May 2022), "DeepMind's new AI can perform over 600 tasks, from playing games to controlling robots"TechCruncharchivedfrom the original on 16 June 2022, retrieved 12 June 2022
  64. ^ Sandberg & Boström 2008. "The basic idea is to take a particular brain, scan its structure in detail, and construct a software model of it that is so faithful to the original that, when run on appropriate hardware, it will behave in essentially the same way as the original brain."
  65. ^ Sandberg & Boström 2008.
  66. ^ Drachman 2005.
  67. Jump up to:a b Russell & Norvig 2003.
  68. ^ Moravec 1988, p. 61.
  69. Jump up to:a b Moravec 1998.
  70. ^ Swaminathan, Nikhil (January–February 2011). "Glia—the other brain cells"DiscoverArchived from the original on 8 February 2014. Retrieved 24 January 2014.
  71. ^ Izhikevich, Eugene M.; Edelman, Gerald M. (4 March 2008). "Large-scale model of mammalian thalamocortical systems" (PDF)PNAS105 (9): 3593–3598. Bibcode:2008PNAS..105.3593Idoi:10.1073/pnas.0712231105PMC 2265160PMID 18292226. Archived from the original (PDF) on 12 June 2009. Retrieved 23 June2015.
  72. ^ "Project Milestones"Blue Brain. Retrieved 11 August 2008.
  73. ^ "Artificial brain '10 years away'"BBC News. 22 July 2009. Archivedfrom the original on 26 July 2017. Retrieved 25 July 2009.
  74. ^ University of Calgary news Archived 18 August 2009 at the Wayback MachineNBC News news Archived 4 July 2017 at the Wayback Machine
  75. ^ de Vega, Glenberg & Graesser 2008. A wide range of views in current research, all of which require grounding to some degree
  76. ^ "[links to bee brain studies]"Honey Bee Brain. Archived from the original on 25 July 2008. Retrieved 30 March 2010.
  77. Jump up to:a b Yudkowsky 2006.
  78. ^ Yekutieli, Y; Sagiv-Zohar, R; Aharonov, R; Engel, Y; Hochner, B; Flash, T(August 2005). "Dynamic model of the octopus arm. I. Biomechanics of the octopus reaching movement". J. Neurophysiol94 (2): 1443–58. doi:10.1152/jn.00684.2004PMID 15829594.
  79. ^ Williams & Herrup 1988
  80. ^ "nervous system, human." Encyclopædia Britannica. 9 January 2007
  81. ^ Azevedo et al. 2009.
  82. ^ Searle 1980
  83. ^ For example:
  84. Jump up to:a b c Russell & Norvig 2003, p. 947.
  85. ^ Nagel 1974.
  86. Jump up to:a b c Sotala, Kaj; Yampolskiy, Roman V. (19 December 2014). "Responses to catastrophic AGI risk: a survey"Physica Scripta90 (1): 018001. doi:10.1088/0031-8949/90/1/018001ISSN 0031-8949.
  87. ^ Joy, Bill (April 2000). "Why the future doesn't need us". Wired.
  88. ^ Aleksander 1996.
  89. Jump up to:a b c d e f g h i Clocksin 2003.
  90. ^ James, Alex P. (2022). "The Why , What , and How of Artificial General Intelligence Chip Development"IEEE Transactions on Cognitive and Developmental Systems14 (2): 333–347. arXiv:2012.06338doi:10.1109/TCDS.2021.3069871ISSN 2379-8920S2CID 228376556Archived from the original on 28 August 2022. Retrieved 28 August 2022.
  91. ^ Pei, Jing; Deng, Lei; Song, Sen; Zhao, Mingguo; Zhang, Youhui; Wu, Shuang; Wang, Guanrui; Zou, Zhe; Wu, Zhenzhi; He, Wei; Chen, Feng; Deng, Ning; Wu, Si; Wang, Yu; Wu, Yujie (2019). "Towards artificial general intelligence with hybrid Tianjic chip architecture"Nature572 (7767): 106–111. Bibcode:2019Natur.572..106Pdoi:10.1038/s41586-019-1424-8ISSN 1476-4687PMID 31367028S2CID 199056116Archivedfrom the original on 29 August 2022. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  92. Jump up to:a b c d Gelernter 2010.
  93. ^ Strickland, Eliza (2021). "The Turbulent Past and Uncertain Future of AI: Is there a way out of AI's boom-and-bust cycle?"IEEE Spectrum58 (10): 26–31. doi:10.1109/mspec.2021.9563956ISSN 0018-9235S2CID 238478853.
  94. Jump up to:a b c McCarthy 2007.
  95. ^ Yamakawa, Hiroshi (2021). "The whole brain architecture approach: Accelerating the development of artificial general intelligence by referring to the brain"Neural Networks144: 478–495. doi:10.1016/j.neunet.2021.09.004ISSN 0893-6080PMID 34600220S2CID 232170707.
  96. ^ Jones, David T.; Kerber, Kevin A. (7 February 2022). "Artificial Intelligence and the Practice of Neurology in 2035"Neurology98 (6): 238–245. doi:10.1212/wnl.0000000000013200ISSN 0028-3878PMID 35131918S2CID 246635279Archived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 28 August 2022.
  97. Jump up to:a b c d Holte & Choueiry 2003.
  98. ^ Zucker 2003.
  99. ^ Deane, George (2022). "Machines That Feel and Think: The Role of Affective Feelings and Mental Action in (Artificial) General Intelligence"Artificial Life28 (3): 289–309. doi:10.1162/artl_a_00368ISSN 1064-5462PMID 35881678S2CID 251069071.
  100. ^ Kaplan, Andreas; Haenlein, Michael (2019). "Kaplan Andreas and Haelein Michael (2019) Siri, Siri, in my hand: Who's the fairest in the land? On the interpretations, illustrations, and implications of artificial intelligence". Business Horizons62: 15–25. doi:10.1016/j.bushor.2018.08.004S2CID 158433736.
  101. ^ Priyadarshini, Ishaani; Cotton, Chase (2022). "AI Cannot Understand Memes: Experiments with OCR and Facial Emotions"Computers, Materials & Continua70 (1): 781–800. doi:10.32604/cmc.2022.019284ISSN 1546-2226S2CID 239639188Archived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 28 August 2022.
  102. ^ Boucher, Philip (March 2019). "Concluding remarks". How artificial intelligence works (PDF) (Report). European Parliamentary Research Service. Archived (PDF) from the original on 3 March 2020. Retrieved 3 March 2020Today's AI is powerful and useful, but remains far from speculated AGI or ASI.
  103. ^ itu.int: Beyond Mad?: The Race For Artificial General IntelligenceArchived 9 November 2020 at the Wayback Machine, "AGI represents a level of power that remains firmly in the realm of speculative fiction as on date." February 2, 2018, retrieved March 3, 2020
  104. ^ Allen, Paul; Greaves, Mark (12 October 2011). "The Singularity Isn't Near"MIT Technology Review. Retrieved 17 September 2014.
  105. ^ Winfield, Alan. "Artificial intelligence will not turn into a Frankenstein's monster"The GuardianArchived from the original on 17 September 2014. Retrieved 17 September 2014.
  106. ^ Fjelland, Ragnar (17 June 2020). "Why general artificial intelligence will not be realized"Humanities and Social Sciences Communications7 (1): 1–9. doi:10.1057/s41599-020-0494-4ISSN 2662-9992S2CID 219710554.
  107. ^ Raffi Khatchadourian (23 November 2015). "The Doomsday Invention: Will artificial intelligence bring us utopia or destruction?"The New YorkerArchived from the original on 28 January 2016. Retrieved 7 February 2016.
  108. ^ Müller, V. C., & Bostrom, N. (2016). Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion. In Fundamental issues of artificial intelligence (pp. 555–572). Springer, Cham.
  109. ^ Brooks, Rodney (11 November 2014). "AI is a tool, not a threat"RobohubArchived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 31 May2022.
  110. ^ Müller, Vincent C. (3 July 2014). "Risks of general artificial intelligence"Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence26 (3): 297–301. doi:10.1080/0952813X.2014.895110ISSN 0952-813XS2CID 31835019.
  111. ^ Turchin, Alexey (1 March 2019). "Assessing the future plausibility of catastrophically dangerous AI"Futures107: 45–58. doi:10.1016/j.futures.2018.11.007ISSN 0016-3287S2CID 158975847.
  112. ^ Rawlinson, Kevin. "Microsoft's Bill Gates insists AI is a threat"BBC NewsArchived from the original on 29 January 2015. Retrieved 30 January 2015.
  113. ^ "Stephen Hawking: 'Transcendence looks at the implications of artificial intelligence – but are we taking AI seriously enough?'"The Independent (UK)Archived from the original on 25 September 2015. Retrieved 3 December 2014.
  114. ^ McLean, Scott; Read, Gemma J. M.; Thompson, Jason; Baber, Chris; Stanton, Neville A.; Salmon, Paul M. (13 August 2021). "The risks associated with Artificial General Intelligence: A systematic review"Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence: 1–15. doi:10.1080/0952813X.2021.1964003ISSN 0952-813XS2CID 238643957.
  115. ^ Bostrom, Nick (2014). Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies(First ed.). ISBN 978-0199678112.
  116. ^ Naudé, Wim; Dimitri, Nicola (1 June 2020). "The race for an artificial general intelligence: implications for public policy"AI & Society35 (2): 367–379. doi:10.1007/s00146-019-00887-xISSN 1435-5655S2CID 52045822.
  117. ^ Torres, Phil (4 May 2019). "The possibility and risks of artificial general intelligence"Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists75 (3): 105–108. Bibcode:2019BuAtS..75c.105Tdoi:10.1080/00963402.2019.1604873ISSN 0096-3402S2CID 150498464Archived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  118. ^ Turchin, Alexey; Denkenberger, David (27 July 2018), "Military AI as a Convergent Goal of Self-Improving AI"Artificial Intelligence Safety and Security, First edition. | Boca Raton, FL : CRC Press/Taylor & Francis Group, 2018.: Chapman and Hall/CRC, pp. 375–393, doi:10.1201/9781351251389-25ISBN 978-1-351-25138-9S2CID 65323952archived from the original on 2 February 2023, retrieved 29 August 2022
  119. ^ Carayannis, Elias G.; Draper, John (11 January 2022). "Optimising peace through a Universal Global Peace Treaty to constrain the risk of war from a militarised artificial superintelligence"AI & Society: 1–14. doi:10.1007/s00146-021-01382-yISSN 1435-5655PMC 8748529PMID 35035113Archived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  120. ^ Hamblin, James (9 May 2014). "But What Would the End of Humanity Mean for Me?"The AtlanticArchived from the original on 4 June 2014. Retrieved 12 December 2015.
  121. ^ "Tech Luminaries Address Singularity"IEEE Spectrum: Technology, Engineering, and Science News. No. SPECIAL REPORT: THE SINGULARITY. 1 June 2008. Archived from the original on 30 April 2019. Retrieved 8 April 2020.
  122. ^ Shermer, Michael (1 March 2017). "Apocalypse AI"Scientific American316 (3): 77. Bibcode:2017SciAm.316c..77Sdoi:10.1038/scientificamerican0317-77PMID 28207698Archivedfrom the original on 1 December 2017. Retrieved 27 November 2017.

Sources[edit]

External links[edit]